References

Bahadur G The Human Rights Act (1998) and its impact on reproductive issues.. Hum Reprod. 2001; 16:(4)785-789 https://doi.org/10.1093/humrep/16.4.785

Bhattacharya S, Ghosh C, Khan I, Shrotri M Legal support to gain access to medical treatment in the current healthcare system is unproductive.. Med Leg J. 2019; 87:(2)85-88 https://doi.org/10.1177/0025817219845242

Bridgeman J A threshold of significant harm (f)or a viable alternative therapeutic option?. J Med Ethics. 2018; 44:(7)466-470 https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2017-104720

Dyer C Children's hospital must be allowed to withdraw life support from Alfie Evans, court rules.. BMJ. 2018; 361 https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.k1773

Freckelton I Futility of treatment for dying children: lessons from the Charlie Gard Case.. J Law Med. 2017; 25:(1)7-29

General Medical Council. 2013. https://tinyurl.com/y695hu8q

Gillon R Defending the four principles approach as a good basis for good medical practice and therefore for good medical ethics.. J Med Ethics. 2015; 41:(1)111-116 https://doi.org/10.1136/medethics-2014-102282

Griffith R Lawfully withdrawing life-sustaining treatment.. Br J Community Nurs. 2013; 18:(12)616-619 https://doi.org/10.12968/bjcn.2013.18.12.616

Howard DS, Pawlik TM Withdrawing medically futile treatment.. J Oncol Pract. 2009; 5:(4)193-195 https://doi.org/10.1200/JOP.0948501

Maclean AR The Human Rights Act 1998 and the individual's right to treatment.. Med Law Int. 2000; 4:(3-4)245-276

McPherson K, Carlos WG, Emmett TW, Slaven JE, Torke AM Limitation of life-sustaining care in the critically ill: a systematic review of the literature.. J Hosp Med. 2019; 14:(5)303-310 https://doi.org/10.12788/jhm.3137

Paris JJ, Ahluwalia J, Cummings BM, Moreland MP, Wilkinson DJ The Charlie Gard case: British and American approaches to court resolution of disputes over medical decisions.. J Perinatol. 2017; 37:(12)1268-1271 https://doi.org/10.1038/jp.2017.138

Samanta J, Samanta A In search of a good death: Human Rights Act 1998 imposes an obligation to facilitate a good death.. BMJ. 2003; 327:(7408) https://doi.org/10.1136/bmj.327.7408.225-a

Samanta A, Samanta J The Human Rights Act 1998: why should it matter for medical practice?. J R Soc Med. 2005; 98:(9)404-410 https://doi.org/10.1258/jrsm.98.9.404

Welie JVM, ten Have HAMJ The ethics of forgoing lifesustaining treatment: theoretical considerations and clinical decision making.. Multidiscip Respir Med. 2014; 9:(1) https://doi.org/10.1186/2049-6958-9-14

Winter SM Terminal nutrition: framing the debate for the withdrawal of nutritional support in terminally ill patients.. Am J Med. 2000; 109:(9)723-726 https://doi.org/10.1016/s0002-9343(00)00609-4

Woogara J Human rights and patients' privacy in UK hospitals.. Nurs Ethics. 2001; 8:(3)234-246 https://doi.org/10.1177/096973300100800308

Dilemmas faced by health professionals surrounding life-sustaining treatment

24 October 2019
Volume 28 · Issue 19

Health professionals often face significant dilemmas while considering the validity of offering or continuing life-sustaining treatment in critical patients (McPherson et al, 2019).

Since the inception of the Human Rights Act 1998, there has been great deal of speculation regarding its impact on medical decision-making, although the true effect may be unknown until a body of case law has developed, illustrating how the legal system interprets the Act (Maclean, 2000; Bahadur, 2001; Woogara, 2001). What is clear, however, is that this Act does not represent anything new, but only reflects, very closely, the existing General Medical Council (GMC) guidelines of Good Medical Practice (GMC, 2013).

Historically, clinical decisions were based upon ethical standards on issues surrounding human dignity and were guided by patients’ consent and best interests. These are largely compliant with the Act. In the future there will be multiple instances where this legislation will be used to challenge medical decisions. It is therefore essential for clinicians to take account of these regulations, ensure their decision-making is transparent and be prepared to withstand scrutiny (Samanta and Samanta, 2005; Gillon, 2015).

It could be argued that a health professional should take adequate measures where ‘right to life’ is at risk, and that withholding any life-sustaining treatment could be deemed as a breach of article 2 of the Act. However, this comes with certain caveats. The Act is constrained by the concept of ‘futility’. If treatment is deemed to be ineffective and arguably would increase a patient's distress, withholding it would not breach article 2 (Samanta and Samanta, 2003; Howard and Pawlik, 2009). Futility, however, needs appropriate validation by a suitable panel of experts prior to treatment withdrawal, on a case-by-case basis. In Burke v GMC, the court made it clear that such decisions should be based on patients’ best interests, were not to be taken by doctors alone behind closed doors, but rather should be a multidisciplinary decision (involving next-of-kin), based upon ‘welfare appraisal in the widest sense, taking account, where appropriate, [of] a wide range of ethical, social, moral, emotional and welfare considerations’ (R (on the Application of Burke) v General Medical Council, 2004).

In the case of a 19-month-old, ‘I’, suffering from an irreversible lung condition, progressive multi-organ failure with poor life-expectancy, experts advised nonresuscitation in the event of cardiorespiratory arrest, with palliative care to ease his suffering and permit his life to end with dignity. Ruling on this case, Mr Justice Cazalet stated that this decision was in the child's best interest as further prolongation of treatment would only add to his suffering, hence Article 2 was not infringed (A National Health Service Trust v D & Ors, 2000). Futility thus supports withdrawing of life-prolonging treatment (artificial nutrition, hydration) where non-treatment is in the patient's best interests as in the cases of ‘Mrs H’ and ‘Mrs M’ (NHS Trust A v H; NHS Trust B v M, 2000), who were both in a persistent vegetative state (Winter, 2000; Griffith, 2013; Welie and ten Have, 2014).

In the present day, a great deal of controversy exists where ‘potentially’ life-saving treatment (expensive drugs or treatment elsewhere) is refused on grounds of scarce resources or lack of evidence that such treatment would be effective, especially if there is a hint of rationing of services (Paris et al, 2017; Bhattacharya et al, 2019). In deciding on these cases, health authorities must be able to justify interfering with a patient's article 2 rights, be transparent, logical, non-discriminatory and able to withstand scrutiny. Unsurprisingly, such decisions are frequently challenged. In three cases—Charlie Gard, a child with leukaemia in Cambridge Health Authority, and Alfie Evans—courts upheld the decision of the respective health authorities as the potential life-saving treatments were deemed to be experimental at best (R v Cambridge Health Authority, 1995; Freckelton, 2017; Great Ormond Street Hospital v Yates, Gard and Gard, 2017; Paris et al, 2017; Alder Hey NHS Trust v Evans, 2018; Bridgeman, 2018; Dyer, 2018).

The following issues seem to be pertinent. Firstly, the definition of a patient's best interest at any point in time rests upon the fine balance between ‘right to life’ versus ‘futility’. However, are these two separated by a well-defined line or a ‘grey zone’? I believe, in many cases, it is the latter, leading to extensive medico-legal debate. Having to explain the concept of futility to a patient's loved ones is often a clinician's worst nightmare. Hence, where possible, such decisions should be based upon hard facts—establishing failure to respond to ongoing treatment and how the burden of ongoing treatment is negatively affecting the patient's quality of life—rather than presumptive evidence. As stated above, health professionals should also be prepared to defend their decisions from a medico-legal perspective.

Secondly, in the current cash-strapped healthcare system, futility has been used to defend medical rationing (Bhattacharya et al, 2019), especially when evidence supporting novel treatments are weak. The cases of Charlie Gard and Alfie Evans, discussed above, point towards such trends. It is important to remember, however, that the evidence obtained from the treatment of rare diseases takes a long time to be established in the form of guidelines. Therefore health authorities tend to base their decision of ‘futility’ in current patients on historic evidence and personal views, which may be questionable and therefore are likely to encounter legal challenges.

In my opinion, when it comes to rare disorders, the medical fraternity should keep a more open mind with regard to treatment options, although the feasibility of undertaking the cost of such interventions are often a challenge in a publicly funded healthcare system. This remains an area of debate.

In summary, although the right to life is upheld by the law, special circumstances may arise where treatment withdrawal is dictated by the overall best interests of patients and multidisciplinary decision-making by health professionals.